IMMANUEL KANT – BASIC INFORMATION AND KNOWLEDGE BANK


A Short Biography Immanuel Kant

Who is Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)?
German philosopher. Kant was born and died at Königsberg, East Prussia. His philosophical reputation rests on the three Critiques-Pure Reason (1781), Practical Reason (1788) and Judgment (1790).
In 1785 he published the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, which first set forth the celebrated categorical imperative always to have a 'good will', to treat persons as ends in themselves, never merely as means to arbitrary ends. Kant's political thought was developed after the French Revolution in Toward Eternal Peace (1795), the Metaphysical Elements of Justice (1797), and The Conflict of the Faculties (1798); its central idea is that politics must 'bend the knee' to morality.

It is plainly Kant's central political conviction that morality and politics must be related, since 'true politics cannot take a single step without first paying homage to morals'. At the same time, however, Kant drew a very strict distinction between moral motives (acting from good will or respect for the moral law) and legal motives, and insisted that moral and legal incentives must never be collapsed into each other; this is why he argued (in The Conflict of the Faculties) that even with growing 'enlightenment' and 'republicanism' there still will not be a greater quantity of moral actions in the world, but only a large number of legal ones which roughly correspond to what pure morality would achieve if it could. (At the end of time, a purely moral 'kingdom of ends' will predictably not be realized on earth—though it ought to be—but one can reasonably hope for a better legal order which is closer to morality than are present arrangements.) Morality and public legal justice must be related in such a way that morality shapes politics—by forbidding war, by insisting on 'eternal peace' and the 'rights of man'—without becoming the motive of politics (since politics cannot hope for 'good will').

Given this tension between a morality and a public legal justice which must be related but which equally must remain distinct, it may be that the notion of 'ends' can help to serve as a bridge: for public law certainly upholds some moral ends (e.g. no murder), even though that law must content itself with a legal motive.

Using teleology as a bridge connecting the moral to the political-legal realm is not a very radical innovation, since Kant himself used 'ends' in the Critique of Judgment to unite his whole philosophy. He did this by arguing that nature can be estimated (though never known) through purposes and functions which mechanical causality fails to explain, that persons as free agents both have purposes which they strive to realize and view themselves as the final end of creation, and that art exhibits a 'purposiveness without purpose' which makes it (not directly moral but) the symbol of morality. Surely, then, if ends can link—or be thought of as linking—nature, human freedom and art, they can link (much more modestly) two sides of human freedom: namely the moral and the legal realms.

Now if 'good will', in the moral realm, could mean never universalizing a maxim of action which would fail to respect persons as ends in themselves, then morality and politics—law could be connected through Kantian teleology. If all persons had a good will, then they would respect all others as ends—indeed as members of a 'kingdom of ends'; but, although it ought to, this does not actually happen, thanks to the

pathological fact that man is radically evil. If, in sum, good will means respect for persons as ends in themselves, and if public legal justice sees to it that some moral ends (such as non-murder) get observed, if not respected, then public legal justice in Kant might be viewed as the partial realization of what would happen if all wills were good. In addition Kant frequently suggests that law creates a kind of environment for good will, by bracketing out occasions of political sin (such as fear of others' domination) which might tempt (though never determine) people to act wrongly.

Perhaps Kant's whole position on politics as the legal realization of moral ends is best summed up in

Man in the system of nature . . . is of little significance and, along with the other animals, considered as products of the earth, has an ordinary value . . . But man as a person, i.e. as the subject of a morally practical reason, is exalted above all price. For as such a one (homo noumenon) he is not to be valued merely as a means to the ends of other people, or even to his own ends, but is to be prized as an end in himself.

In The Conflict of the Faculties Kant translated this very passage—or so it almost seems—into the language of politics:

In the face of omnipotence of nature, or rather its supreme first cause which is inaccessible to us, the human being is, in his turn, but a trifle. But for the sovereigns of his own species also to consider and treat him as such, whether by burdening him as an animal, regarding him as a mere tool of their designs, or exposing him in their conflicts with one another in order to have him massacred—this is no trifle, but a subversion of the ultimate purpose of creation itself. (See Political Writings, p. 185.)

On this teleological view, sovereigns deny the rights of man (or perhaps more properly the rights of persons) by treating men as mere means to a relative purpose (e.g. territorial aggrandizement); in Kant's view war, which necessarily treats men as mere means to an immoral purpose, causes the state to attack and subvert morality, when in fact the state and the legal order ought (as qualified goods) to provide a stable context of peace and security within which men can safely exercise the sole unqualified good, a 'good will'. 

So the notion that persons are ends who ought never to be used merely as means to arbitrary purposes provides 'good will' with an objective end which is the source of the categorical imperative, and it sets a limiting condition to what politics can legitimately do. Despite what HEGEL says, then, Kantianism is not merely a formal doctrine in which (to quote Hegel's language) 'chill duty is the final undigested lump left within the stomach'.

Kant is clear, moreover, that citizens (not mere subjects) in a republic would dissent from war, out of the legal motive of self-love. Therefore republicanism (internally) and eternal peace (externally) are interlocked, absolutely inseparable. This is why Kant says that in 'a constitution where the subject is not a citizen, and which is therefore not republican, it is the simplest thing in the world to go to war'—despite the fact that 'reason as the highest legislative moral power, absolutely condemns war as a test of rights'. 

Therefore republican citizenship is instrumental to an essential moral end that good will alone may never realize, thanks to human pathology. For Kant, the outside is shaped by the inside; it is that which leads him to say that the first definitive article of eternal peace is that 'the civil constitution of every state shall be republican'.

All of this is brought out by Kant himself in the splendid last pages of the Metaphysical Elements of Justice:
Moral-practical reason within us pronounces the following irresistible veto: There shall be no war, either between individual human beings in the state of nature, or between separate states, which, although internally law-governed, still live in a lawless condition in their external relationships with one another. 

For war is not the way in which anyone should pursue his rights . . . It can indeed be said that this task of establishing a universal and lasting peace is not just a part of the theory of right within the limits of pure reason, but its entire ultimate purpose (Endzweck) (See Political Writings, p. 174.)

This simply confirms, and ties together, what has been said above: that it is morality itself that vetoes war (doubtless because war treats ends as mere means, persons as mere things); that peace as a moral end can be legally approached by establishing that constitution (namely 'republicanism in all states, individually and collectively') that brings self-loving rational citizens to veto war; that to think that the moral law that forbids war might be misleading is to renounce reason and to fall back on the 'mechanism of nature'; that right, which legally realizes some moral ends (even without good will), has universal and lasting peace as its 'entire ultimate purpose' (Endzweck) It is doubtful whether there is any other passage, anywhere in Kant, that so vividly and movingly fills out his notion of a politics that pays homage to the ends of morals. 

It is a passage whose visionary but sane breadth redeems the drier parts of the Metaphysical Elements of Justice. And it confirms what should never have been doubted: that Kant is a political philosopher of the very first rank whose evolutionary political goals would, if actually realized, constitute a valuable revolution in history. 

No comments:

Post a Comment